How do I prove the transitivity of a set of implications?
$begingroup$
If I have a set of implications, how can I prove the transitivity? In other words: I know the transitivity law, but I need to show on paper for an assignment whether the argument is valid or not.
$$
begin{align}
P&to Q\
Q&to R \
therefore P&to R
end{align}
$$
I recall something to do with assuming P and/or Q, since $Pto Q$ will always be true if P is false anyhow, and the same with $Qto R$... but I don't know how to do it on paper.
logic propositional-calculus
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If I have a set of implications, how can I prove the transitivity? In other words: I know the transitivity law, but I need to show on paper for an assignment whether the argument is valid or not.
$$
begin{align}
P&to Q\
Q&to R \
therefore P&to R
end{align}
$$
I recall something to do with assuming P and/or Q, since $Pto Q$ will always be true if P is false anyhow, and the same with $Qto R$... but I don't know how to do it on paper.
logic propositional-calculus
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If I have a set of implications, how can I prove the transitivity? In other words: I know the transitivity law, but I need to show on paper for an assignment whether the argument is valid or not.
$$
begin{align}
P&to Q\
Q&to R \
therefore P&to R
end{align}
$$
I recall something to do with assuming P and/or Q, since $Pto Q$ will always be true if P is false anyhow, and the same with $Qto R$... but I don't know how to do it on paper.
logic propositional-calculus
$endgroup$
If I have a set of implications, how can I prove the transitivity? In other words: I know the transitivity law, but I need to show on paper for an assignment whether the argument is valid or not.
$$
begin{align}
P&to Q\
Q&to R \
therefore P&to R
end{align}
$$
I recall something to do with assuming P and/or Q, since $Pto Q$ will always be true if P is false anyhow, and the same with $Qto R$... but I don't know how to do it on paper.
logic propositional-calculus
logic propositional-calculus
edited Jan 19 '13 at 16:10
Namaste
1
1
asked Jan 17 '13 at 18:17
agent154agent154
3,752216599
3,752216599
add a comment |
add a comment |
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
$$(1) Prightarrow Qtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$(2) Qrightarrow Rtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$quadquadunderline{(3); Pquad }tag{Assumption}$$
$$quad quadquad |(4) Q tag{1 and 3: Modus Ponens}$$
$$quadquadquad |(5) R tag{2 and 4: Modus Ponens}$$
$$(6) P rightarrow R tag{3 - 5: if P, then R}$$
$$therefore ((Prightarrow Q)land (Qrightarrow R))rightarrow (Pto R)$$
(Note: step 6 is sometimes justified by "conditional introduction": together with what you are given or have established, if by assuming P, you can derive R, then you have shown $P rightarrow R$).
Note: when I first learned propositional logic, once it was established (proven), we referred to the following "syllogism":
$$Pto Q\
underline{Qto R}\
therefore Pto Rquad$$
by citing it as the "Hypothetical Syllogism", for justification in future proofs.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since the logic you are using is not quantified, and there are only three variables, you can prove the argument valid with an eight row truth table covering all of the possible truth values of the three variables:
P Q R Premise: P -> Q Premise: Q -> R: Conclusion: P -> R
------------------------------------------------------------------------
0 0 0 1 1 1
0 0 1 1 1 1
0 1 0 1 0 1
0 1 1 1 1 1
1 0 0 0 1 0
1 0 1 0 1 1
1 1 0 1 0 0
1 1 1 1 1 1
Now an argument is valid if the conclusion is true whenever all the premises are true.
This means that in all the rows where both premises have a 1, we check whether the conclusion has a 1. By golly, this is the case. Therefore the argument is valid!
If we found a zero, that would be a counterexample which destroys the argument: a situation where the premises are all true, yet the conclusion is false.
In my table, the P -> Q
column and its siblings are simply derived from the truth table for the conditional. P -> Q
is only false when P is true, and Q is false, and true for the other three possible values of the variables.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm not sure about what notations you might use nor if you're using a natural deductive system, but this is the idea behind what you asked:
Suppose $Pto Q\
Qto R\$ are true.
We want to prove that $Pto R$ is true.
To do this suppose $P$ is true.
Because $Pto Q$ is true it follows that $Q$ is true.
Now because $Q$ is true, from $Qto R$ being true follows that $R$ is true.
We assumed $P$ was true and we deduced that $R$ is also true, therefore $Pto R$ as we wanted.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Although it is late, I wanted to give a simple and convincing demonstration:
(1) P -> Q (Hypothesis)
(2) Q -> R (Hypothesis)
(3) ¬Q -> ¬P (Contraposition (1))
(4) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) (Union (2) and (3))
(5) Q ∨ ¬Q (Law of excluded middle)
(6) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) ∧ ( Q ∨ ¬Q) (Union (4) and (5) )
____________________________
(R ∨ ¬P) (Dilemma of (6), P -> R=def.(R ∨ ¬P) Definition of logical implication)
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Denote by $+$ the $or$ logic operator and by $cdot$ the $and$ logic operator.
We have $(ARightarrow B)=bar A+B$ and $(BRightarrow C) =bar B+C$
Assume $(bar A + B)=1=(bar B+C)$.
Then
$1=1cdot 1=(bar A + B)cdot (bar B+C) \
= (bar Abar B + bar A C + Bbar B + BC)\
= bar A + BC
= (bar A + B) cdot (bar A+C)
\
=bar A + C
$
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The answer for $6$ is indeed, true but if you had to show it with a truth table would be as follows
$$begin{array}{cccccccc}P & Q & R & P!rightarrow! Q & Q!rightarrow! R & P!rightarrow! R & (P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R) & [(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)]!rightarrow! (P!rightarrow! R)\
T & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
T & T & F & T & F & F & F & T\
T & F & T & F & T & T & F & T\
T & F & F & F & T & F & F & T\
F & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & T & F & T & F & T & F & T\
F & F & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & F & F & T & T & T & T & Tend{array}$$
As you notice above the column $(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)$ is the same as the column of $(P!rightarrow! R).$ So with both the hypotheses $(P!rightarrow! R)$ and $(Q!rightarrow! R)$ we can conclude that $(P!rightarrow! R).$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f280893%2fhow-do-i-prove-the-transitivity-of-a-set-of-implications%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
6 Answers
6
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
$$(1) Prightarrow Qtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$(2) Qrightarrow Rtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$quadquadunderline{(3); Pquad }tag{Assumption}$$
$$quad quadquad |(4) Q tag{1 and 3: Modus Ponens}$$
$$quadquadquad |(5) R tag{2 and 4: Modus Ponens}$$
$$(6) P rightarrow R tag{3 - 5: if P, then R}$$
$$therefore ((Prightarrow Q)land (Qrightarrow R))rightarrow (Pto R)$$
(Note: step 6 is sometimes justified by "conditional introduction": together with what you are given or have established, if by assuming P, you can derive R, then you have shown $P rightarrow R$).
Note: when I first learned propositional logic, once it was established (proven), we referred to the following "syllogism":
$$Pto Q\
underline{Qto R}\
therefore Pto Rquad$$
by citing it as the "Hypothetical Syllogism", for justification in future proofs.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$$(1) Prightarrow Qtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$(2) Qrightarrow Rtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$quadquadunderline{(3); Pquad }tag{Assumption}$$
$$quad quadquad |(4) Q tag{1 and 3: Modus Ponens}$$
$$quadquadquad |(5) R tag{2 and 4: Modus Ponens}$$
$$(6) P rightarrow R tag{3 - 5: if P, then R}$$
$$therefore ((Prightarrow Q)land (Qrightarrow R))rightarrow (Pto R)$$
(Note: step 6 is sometimes justified by "conditional introduction": together with what you are given or have established, if by assuming P, you can derive R, then you have shown $P rightarrow R$).
Note: when I first learned propositional logic, once it was established (proven), we referred to the following "syllogism":
$$Pto Q\
underline{Qto R}\
therefore Pto Rquad$$
by citing it as the "Hypothetical Syllogism", for justification in future proofs.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
$$(1) Prightarrow Qtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$(2) Qrightarrow Rtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$quadquadunderline{(3); Pquad }tag{Assumption}$$
$$quad quadquad |(4) Q tag{1 and 3: Modus Ponens}$$
$$quadquadquad |(5) R tag{2 and 4: Modus Ponens}$$
$$(6) P rightarrow R tag{3 - 5: if P, then R}$$
$$therefore ((Prightarrow Q)land (Qrightarrow R))rightarrow (Pto R)$$
(Note: step 6 is sometimes justified by "conditional introduction": together with what you are given or have established, if by assuming P, you can derive R, then you have shown $P rightarrow R$).
Note: when I first learned propositional logic, once it was established (proven), we referred to the following "syllogism":
$$Pto Q\
underline{Qto R}\
therefore Pto Rquad$$
by citing it as the "Hypothetical Syllogism", for justification in future proofs.
$endgroup$
$$(1) Prightarrow Qtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$(2) Qrightarrow Rtag{Hypothesis}$$
$$quadquadunderline{(3); Pquad }tag{Assumption}$$
$$quad quadquad |(4) Q tag{1 and 3: Modus Ponens}$$
$$quadquadquad |(5) R tag{2 and 4: Modus Ponens}$$
$$(6) P rightarrow R tag{3 - 5: if P, then R}$$
$$therefore ((Prightarrow Q)land (Qrightarrow R))rightarrow (Pto R)$$
(Note: step 6 is sometimes justified by "conditional introduction": together with what you are given or have established, if by assuming P, you can derive R, then you have shown $P rightarrow R$).
Note: when I first learned propositional logic, once it was established (proven), we referred to the following "syllogism":
$$Pto Q\
underline{Qto R}\
therefore Pto Rquad$$
by citing it as the "Hypothetical Syllogism", for justification in future proofs.
edited Jan 17 '13 at 20:56
answered Jan 17 '13 at 18:41
NamasteNamaste
1
1
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since the logic you are using is not quantified, and there are only three variables, you can prove the argument valid with an eight row truth table covering all of the possible truth values of the three variables:
P Q R Premise: P -> Q Premise: Q -> R: Conclusion: P -> R
------------------------------------------------------------------------
0 0 0 1 1 1
0 0 1 1 1 1
0 1 0 1 0 1
0 1 1 1 1 1
1 0 0 0 1 0
1 0 1 0 1 1
1 1 0 1 0 0
1 1 1 1 1 1
Now an argument is valid if the conclusion is true whenever all the premises are true.
This means that in all the rows where both premises have a 1, we check whether the conclusion has a 1. By golly, this is the case. Therefore the argument is valid!
If we found a zero, that would be a counterexample which destroys the argument: a situation where the premises are all true, yet the conclusion is false.
In my table, the P -> Q
column and its siblings are simply derived from the truth table for the conditional. P -> Q
is only false when P is true, and Q is false, and true for the other three possible values of the variables.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since the logic you are using is not quantified, and there are only three variables, you can prove the argument valid with an eight row truth table covering all of the possible truth values of the three variables:
P Q R Premise: P -> Q Premise: Q -> R: Conclusion: P -> R
------------------------------------------------------------------------
0 0 0 1 1 1
0 0 1 1 1 1
0 1 0 1 0 1
0 1 1 1 1 1
1 0 0 0 1 0
1 0 1 0 1 1
1 1 0 1 0 0
1 1 1 1 1 1
Now an argument is valid if the conclusion is true whenever all the premises are true.
This means that in all the rows where both premises have a 1, we check whether the conclusion has a 1. By golly, this is the case. Therefore the argument is valid!
If we found a zero, that would be a counterexample which destroys the argument: a situation where the premises are all true, yet the conclusion is false.
In my table, the P -> Q
column and its siblings are simply derived from the truth table for the conditional. P -> Q
is only false when P is true, and Q is false, and true for the other three possible values of the variables.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Since the logic you are using is not quantified, and there are only three variables, you can prove the argument valid with an eight row truth table covering all of the possible truth values of the three variables:
P Q R Premise: P -> Q Premise: Q -> R: Conclusion: P -> R
------------------------------------------------------------------------
0 0 0 1 1 1
0 0 1 1 1 1
0 1 0 1 0 1
0 1 1 1 1 1
1 0 0 0 1 0
1 0 1 0 1 1
1 1 0 1 0 0
1 1 1 1 1 1
Now an argument is valid if the conclusion is true whenever all the premises are true.
This means that in all the rows where both premises have a 1, we check whether the conclusion has a 1. By golly, this is the case. Therefore the argument is valid!
If we found a zero, that would be a counterexample which destroys the argument: a situation where the premises are all true, yet the conclusion is false.
In my table, the P -> Q
column and its siblings are simply derived from the truth table for the conditional. P -> Q
is only false when P is true, and Q is false, and true for the other three possible values of the variables.
$endgroup$
Since the logic you are using is not quantified, and there are only three variables, you can prove the argument valid with an eight row truth table covering all of the possible truth values of the three variables:
P Q R Premise: P -> Q Premise: Q -> R: Conclusion: P -> R
------------------------------------------------------------------------
0 0 0 1 1 1
0 0 1 1 1 1
0 1 0 1 0 1
0 1 1 1 1 1
1 0 0 0 1 0
1 0 1 0 1 1
1 1 0 1 0 0
1 1 1 1 1 1
Now an argument is valid if the conclusion is true whenever all the premises are true.
This means that in all the rows where both premises have a 1, we check whether the conclusion has a 1. By golly, this is the case. Therefore the argument is valid!
If we found a zero, that would be a counterexample which destroys the argument: a situation where the premises are all true, yet the conclusion is false.
In my table, the P -> Q
column and its siblings are simply derived from the truth table for the conditional. P -> Q
is only false when P is true, and Q is false, and true for the other three possible values of the variables.
answered Jan 18 '13 at 1:31
KazKaz
6,28311428
6,28311428
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm not sure about what notations you might use nor if you're using a natural deductive system, but this is the idea behind what you asked:
Suppose $Pto Q\
Qto R\$ are true.
We want to prove that $Pto R$ is true.
To do this suppose $P$ is true.
Because $Pto Q$ is true it follows that $Q$ is true.
Now because $Q$ is true, from $Qto R$ being true follows that $R$ is true.
We assumed $P$ was true and we deduced that $R$ is also true, therefore $Pto R$ as we wanted.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm not sure about what notations you might use nor if you're using a natural deductive system, but this is the idea behind what you asked:
Suppose $Pto Q\
Qto R\$ are true.
We want to prove that $Pto R$ is true.
To do this suppose $P$ is true.
Because $Pto Q$ is true it follows that $Q$ is true.
Now because $Q$ is true, from $Qto R$ being true follows that $R$ is true.
We assumed $P$ was true and we deduced that $R$ is also true, therefore $Pto R$ as we wanted.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I'm not sure about what notations you might use nor if you're using a natural deductive system, but this is the idea behind what you asked:
Suppose $Pto Q\
Qto R\$ are true.
We want to prove that $Pto R$ is true.
To do this suppose $P$ is true.
Because $Pto Q$ is true it follows that $Q$ is true.
Now because $Q$ is true, from $Qto R$ being true follows that $R$ is true.
We assumed $P$ was true and we deduced that $R$ is also true, therefore $Pto R$ as we wanted.
$endgroup$
I'm not sure about what notations you might use nor if you're using a natural deductive system, but this is the idea behind what you asked:
Suppose $Pto Q\
Qto R\$ are true.
We want to prove that $Pto R$ is true.
To do this suppose $P$ is true.
Because $Pto Q$ is true it follows that $Q$ is true.
Now because $Q$ is true, from $Qto R$ being true follows that $R$ is true.
We assumed $P$ was true and we deduced that $R$ is also true, therefore $Pto R$ as we wanted.
edited Jan 18 '13 at 16:51
answered Jan 17 '13 at 18:23
Git GudGit Gud
28.9k1050101
28.9k1050101
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
Is this just a form of proof by cases? I guess it's one half of it anyhow - knowing that if we assume $neg P$, the implication will be true no matter what - it's only relevant if we show that it's true if P is true?
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:28
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
No, it's not a proof by cases. What you mentioned is one way to do it: you always have $neg P vee P$, so you do it by cases the way you mentioned. However if you wanna prove a conditional statement, i.e., a statement of the form $Ato B$, it suffices to assume $A$ is true and then somehow deduce that $B$ is true.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:32
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
I just realized - I could convert the implications to clausal form using the rule $(neg Pvee Q)wedge (neg Qvee R)Rightarrow (neg Pvee R)$ and then use the resolution rule to resolve out $(neg Qvee Q)$ to get $neg Pvee R$... That works as well.
$endgroup$
– agent154
Jan 17 '13 at 18:38
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
$begingroup$
Yes, that works too.
$endgroup$
– Git Gud
Jan 17 '13 at 18:39
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Although it is late, I wanted to give a simple and convincing demonstration:
(1) P -> Q (Hypothesis)
(2) Q -> R (Hypothesis)
(3) ¬Q -> ¬P (Contraposition (1))
(4) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) (Union (2) and (3))
(5) Q ∨ ¬Q (Law of excluded middle)
(6) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) ∧ ( Q ∨ ¬Q) (Union (4) and (5) )
____________________________
(R ∨ ¬P) (Dilemma of (6), P -> R=def.(R ∨ ¬P) Definition of logical implication)
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Although it is late, I wanted to give a simple and convincing demonstration:
(1) P -> Q (Hypothesis)
(2) Q -> R (Hypothesis)
(3) ¬Q -> ¬P (Contraposition (1))
(4) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) (Union (2) and (3))
(5) Q ∨ ¬Q (Law of excluded middle)
(6) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) ∧ ( Q ∨ ¬Q) (Union (4) and (5) )
____________________________
(R ∨ ¬P) (Dilemma of (6), P -> R=def.(R ∨ ¬P) Definition of logical implication)
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Although it is late, I wanted to give a simple and convincing demonstration:
(1) P -> Q (Hypothesis)
(2) Q -> R (Hypothesis)
(3) ¬Q -> ¬P (Contraposition (1))
(4) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) (Union (2) and (3))
(5) Q ∨ ¬Q (Law of excluded middle)
(6) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) ∧ ( Q ∨ ¬Q) (Union (4) and (5) )
____________________________
(R ∨ ¬P) (Dilemma of (6), P -> R=def.(R ∨ ¬P) Definition of logical implication)
$endgroup$
Although it is late, I wanted to give a simple and convincing demonstration:
(1) P -> Q (Hypothesis)
(2) Q -> R (Hypothesis)
(3) ¬Q -> ¬P (Contraposition (1))
(4) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) (Union (2) and (3))
(5) Q ∨ ¬Q (Law of excluded middle)
(6) (Q -> R) ∧ (¬Q -> ¬P) ∧ ( Q ∨ ¬Q) (Union (4) and (5) )
____________________________
(R ∨ ¬P) (Dilemma of (6), P -> R=def.(R ∨ ¬P) Definition of logical implication)
answered Jun 2 '17 at 5:49
Roger Figueroa QuinteroRoger Figueroa Quintero
749
749
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Denote by $+$ the $or$ logic operator and by $cdot$ the $and$ logic operator.
We have $(ARightarrow B)=bar A+B$ and $(BRightarrow C) =bar B+C$
Assume $(bar A + B)=1=(bar B+C)$.
Then
$1=1cdot 1=(bar A + B)cdot (bar B+C) \
= (bar Abar B + bar A C + Bbar B + BC)\
= bar A + BC
= (bar A + B) cdot (bar A+C)
\
=bar A + C
$
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Denote by $+$ the $or$ logic operator and by $cdot$ the $and$ logic operator.
We have $(ARightarrow B)=bar A+B$ and $(BRightarrow C) =bar B+C$
Assume $(bar A + B)=1=(bar B+C)$.
Then
$1=1cdot 1=(bar A + B)cdot (bar B+C) \
= (bar Abar B + bar A C + Bbar B + BC)\
= bar A + BC
= (bar A + B) cdot (bar A+C)
\
=bar A + C
$
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Denote by $+$ the $or$ logic operator and by $cdot$ the $and$ logic operator.
We have $(ARightarrow B)=bar A+B$ and $(BRightarrow C) =bar B+C$
Assume $(bar A + B)=1=(bar B+C)$.
Then
$1=1cdot 1=(bar A + B)cdot (bar B+C) \
= (bar Abar B + bar A C + Bbar B + BC)\
= bar A + BC
= (bar A + B) cdot (bar A+C)
\
=bar A + C
$
$endgroup$
Denote by $+$ the $or$ logic operator and by $cdot$ the $and$ logic operator.
We have $(ARightarrow B)=bar A+B$ and $(BRightarrow C) =bar B+C$
Assume $(bar A + B)=1=(bar B+C)$.
Then
$1=1cdot 1=(bar A + B)cdot (bar B+C) \
= (bar Abar B + bar A C + Bbar B + BC)\
= bar A + BC
= (bar A + B) cdot (bar A+C)
\
=bar A + C
$
edited Dec 23 '18 at 17:40
Ben Kushigian
1879
1879
answered Nov 7 '17 at 14:17
SmiliaSmilia
733617
733617
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
$begingroup$
Ha! This is a great argument
$endgroup$
– Ben Kushigian
Dec 23 '18 at 17:17
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The answer for $6$ is indeed, true but if you had to show it with a truth table would be as follows
$$begin{array}{cccccccc}P & Q & R & P!rightarrow! Q & Q!rightarrow! R & P!rightarrow! R & (P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R) & [(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)]!rightarrow! (P!rightarrow! R)\
T & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
T & T & F & T & F & F & F & T\
T & F & T & F & T & T & F & T\
T & F & F & F & T & F & F & T\
F & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & T & F & T & F & T & F & T\
F & F & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & F & F & T & T & T & T & Tend{array}$$
As you notice above the column $(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)$ is the same as the column of $(P!rightarrow! R).$ So with both the hypotheses $(P!rightarrow! R)$ and $(Q!rightarrow! R)$ we can conclude that $(P!rightarrow! R).$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The answer for $6$ is indeed, true but if you had to show it with a truth table would be as follows
$$begin{array}{cccccccc}P & Q & R & P!rightarrow! Q & Q!rightarrow! R & P!rightarrow! R & (P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R) & [(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)]!rightarrow! (P!rightarrow! R)\
T & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
T & T & F & T & F & F & F & T\
T & F & T & F & T & T & F & T\
T & F & F & F & T & F & F & T\
F & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & T & F & T & F & T & F & T\
F & F & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & F & F & T & T & T & T & Tend{array}$$
As you notice above the column $(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)$ is the same as the column of $(P!rightarrow! R).$ So with both the hypotheses $(P!rightarrow! R)$ and $(Q!rightarrow! R)$ we can conclude that $(P!rightarrow! R).$
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The answer for $6$ is indeed, true but if you had to show it with a truth table would be as follows
$$begin{array}{cccccccc}P & Q & R & P!rightarrow! Q & Q!rightarrow! R & P!rightarrow! R & (P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R) & [(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)]!rightarrow! (P!rightarrow! R)\
T & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
T & T & F & T & F & F & F & T\
T & F & T & F & T & T & F & T\
T & F & F & F & T & F & F & T\
F & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & T & F & T & F & T & F & T\
F & F & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & F & F & T & T & T & T & Tend{array}$$
As you notice above the column $(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)$ is the same as the column of $(P!rightarrow! R).$ So with both the hypotheses $(P!rightarrow! R)$ and $(Q!rightarrow! R)$ we can conclude that $(P!rightarrow! R).$
$endgroup$
The answer for $6$ is indeed, true but if you had to show it with a truth table would be as follows
$$begin{array}{cccccccc}P & Q & R & P!rightarrow! Q & Q!rightarrow! R & P!rightarrow! R & (P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R) & [(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)]!rightarrow! (P!rightarrow! R)\
T & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
T & T & F & T & F & F & F & T\
T & F & T & F & T & T & F & T\
T & F & F & F & T & F & F & T\
F & T & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & T & F & T & F & T & F & T\
F & F & T & T & T & T & T & T\
F & F & F & T & T & T & T & Tend{array}$$
As you notice above the column $(P!rightarrow! Q)!wedge!(Q!rightarrow! R)$ is the same as the column of $(P!rightarrow! R).$ So with both the hypotheses $(P!rightarrow! R)$ and $(Q!rightarrow! R)$ we can conclude that $(P!rightarrow! R).$
edited Oct 27 '13 at 17:16
Cameron Buie
87k773161
87k773161
answered Oct 27 '13 at 16:43
John SgutanJohn Sgutan
11
11
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f280893%2fhow-do-i-prove-the-transitivity-of-a-set-of-implications%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown