Can every true theorem that has a proof be proven by contradiction?












18












$begingroup$


After reading and being inspired by, Can every proof by contradiction also be shown without contradiction? and after some thought, I still don't have an answer to this.



Does every theorem with a true proof have a proof by contradiction?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 28




    $begingroup$
    Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:11






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:22






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:26






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:28






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
    $endgroup$
    – Masacroso
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:57


















18












$begingroup$


After reading and being inspired by, Can every proof by contradiction also be shown without contradiction? and after some thought, I still don't have an answer to this.



Does every theorem with a true proof have a proof by contradiction?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$








  • 28




    $begingroup$
    Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:11






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:22






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:26






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:28






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
    $endgroup$
    – Masacroso
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:57
















18












18








18


7



$begingroup$


After reading and being inspired by, Can every proof by contradiction also be shown without contradiction? and after some thought, I still don't have an answer to this.



Does every theorem with a true proof have a proof by contradiction?










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$




After reading and being inspired by, Can every proof by contradiction also be shown without contradiction? and after some thought, I still don't have an answer to this.



Does every theorem with a true proof have a proof by contradiction?







logic proof-writing proof-theory






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Apr 13 '17 at 12:21









Community

1




1










asked Jan 3 '17 at 4:07









TripleATripleA

7421935




7421935








  • 28




    $begingroup$
    Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:11






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:22






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:26






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:28






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
    $endgroup$
    – Masacroso
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:57
















  • 28




    $begingroup$
    Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:11






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:22






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    @Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
    $endgroup$
    – Stahl
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:26






  • 3




    $begingroup$
    I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
    $endgroup$
    – MPW
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:28






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
    $endgroup$
    – Masacroso
    Jan 3 '17 at 4:57










28




28




$begingroup$
Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
$endgroup$
– Stahl
Jan 3 '17 at 4:11




$begingroup$
Let $P$ be a proof of the theorem. Assume the theorem is false. However we can exhibit $P$, which contradicts the assumption.
$endgroup$
– Stahl
Jan 3 '17 at 4:11




3




3




$begingroup$
I think @Stahl is correct
$endgroup$
– MPW
Jan 3 '17 at 4:22




$begingroup$
I think @Stahl is correct
$endgroup$
– MPW
Jan 3 '17 at 4:22




3




3




$begingroup$
@Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
$endgroup$
– Stahl
Jan 3 '17 at 4:26




$begingroup$
@Masacroso note that I did not post it as an answer, but rather as a comment ;) I'm neither a logician nor particularly interested in the subtleties of logic, and I assume someone can and will give a better explanation than I can. However, I have a hunch that one can formalize what I've said.
$endgroup$
– Stahl
Jan 3 '17 at 4:26




3




3




$begingroup$
I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
$endgroup$
– MPW
Jan 3 '17 at 4:28




$begingroup$
I think @Stahl is correct. Many so-called proofs by contradiction amount to assuming the result is false, proceeding to prove the result, then saying that the proven result then contradicts the hypothesis that it is false. It's a classic overkill used by many students when they could just prove the result directly.
$endgroup$
– MPW
Jan 3 '17 at 4:28




1




1




$begingroup$
Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
$endgroup$
– Masacroso
Jan 3 '17 at 4:57






$begingroup$
Ah, sorry, I missread the question as the opposite direction. Anyway it is not clear to me if this is possible or not, I mean that we can construct a proof by contradiction derived from any other proof, but then the status of this proof to be "by contradiction" is not very clear (because the statement is already proved before to "prove it but this derived proof").
$endgroup$
– Masacroso
Jan 3 '17 at 4:57












3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















23












$begingroup$

In classical logic, the answer is yes. Take any theorem $T$ and any proof $P$ for $T$. Now write the following proof:




If $neg T$:



  [Write $P$ here.]



  Thus $T$.



  Thus a contradiction.



Therefore $neg neg T$, by negation introduction.



Thus $T$, by double negation elimination.




One may object that this proof is essentially the same as $P$, and is just wrapped up. That is true, but it is a perfectly legitimate proof of $T$, even if it is longer than $P$, and it is indeed of the form of a proof by contradiction. A natural question that arises is whether the shortest proof of $T$ is a proof by contradiction. That is a much harder question to answer in general, but there are some easy examples, at least for any reasonable natural deduction system.



For instance, the shortest proof of "$A to A$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely not a proof by contradiction but rather just:




If $A$:



$A$.



Therefore $A to A$, by implication introduction.




On the other hand, the shortest proof of "$neg ( A land neg A )$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely a proof by contradiction:




If $A land neg A$:



$A$, by conjunction elimination.



$neg A$, by conjunction elimination.



  Thus a contradiction.



Therefore $neg( A land neg A )$.




The first part of this post shows that the shortest proof by contradiction is at most a few lines longer than the shortest proof, but nothing much else interesting can be said about the shortest proof unless...





Well what if we do not allow the use of double negation elimination? If you have only the other usual rules (the first-order logic rules here but excluding ¬¬elim and including ex falso), then the resulting logic is intuitionistic logic, which is strictly weaker than classical logic, and cannot even prove the law of excluded middle, namely "$A lor neg A$" for any statement $A$. So if you instead ask the more interesting question of whether every true theorem can be proven in intuitionistic logic, then the answer is no.



Note that intuitionistic logic plus the rule "$neg A to bot vdash A$" gives back classical logic, and one could say that this rule embodies the 'true principle' of proof by contradiction, in which case one can say that some true theorems require the use of a proof by contradiction somewhere.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$





















    10












    $begingroup$

    If you can prove a statement $A$ directly, you can prove it by contradiction. Just assume $lnot A$, perform your proof of $A$, note the contradiction, and derive $A$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$





















      1












      $begingroup$

      I find the common thought here unsettling, even if seemingly widely held. Perhaps others share my view, perhaps not (and note, it is just an intuitive view, one which--as explained to me in the comments--isn't in line with the notion of proof!)



      The proof in these purported proofs by contradiction must necessarily rely on the content of the direct proof. Yes, we have ourselves a contradiction, but in a proof by contradiction what convinces us (i.e., what we count as the proof) is not merely that we have a contradiction, but that we have derived a contradiction in a particular manner--from particular assumption(s)--which leads us to conclude something about these assumptions....that they must not be true.



      Here, all we do is prove a statement directly from the premises of the argument, and make a note that our conclusion contradicts the conclusion's_negation--leading us to believe that the negation of the conclusion's_negation (i.e., our conclusion) must be true. We then say to ourselves "aha! Indeed this is the case...since we have already (directly) proven our conclusion to be true!"



      It is not simply that our conclusion need not be derived via contradiction (and that it can be done directly and then "wrapped up" in a so called proof by contradiction), but rather that our conclusion has not been derived in this manner.



      A contradiction arising in a proof does not necessarily warrant that the method of proof being employed is what we call "proof by contradiction." It is the derivation of this contradiction which warrants the name "proof by contradiction." It is how the contradiction arises. And here, our contradiction doesn't really arise so much as the situation is one in which we are pointing out that a directly derived conclusion is contradictory to its negation.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$









      • 2




        $begingroup$
        Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
        $endgroup$
        – Eric Wofsey
        Jan 3 '17 at 23:10






      • 1




        $begingroup$
        The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
        $endgroup$
        – Morgan Rodgers
        Jan 3 '17 at 23:13








      • 1




        $begingroup$
        I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
        $endgroup$
        – Morgan Rodgers
        Jan 4 '17 at 2:28






      • 1




        $begingroup$
        I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
        $endgroup$
        – user21820
        Jan 4 '17 at 5:15






      • 1




        $begingroup$
        The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
        $endgroup$
        – user21820
        Jan 4 '17 at 5:38














      Your Answer








      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2081396%2fcan-every-true-theorem-that-has-a-proof-be-proven-by-contradiction%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes








      3 Answers
      3






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      23












      $begingroup$

      In classical logic, the answer is yes. Take any theorem $T$ and any proof $P$ for $T$. Now write the following proof:




      If $neg T$:



        [Write $P$ here.]



        Thus $T$.



        Thus a contradiction.



      Therefore $neg neg T$, by negation introduction.



      Thus $T$, by double negation elimination.




      One may object that this proof is essentially the same as $P$, and is just wrapped up. That is true, but it is a perfectly legitimate proof of $T$, even if it is longer than $P$, and it is indeed of the form of a proof by contradiction. A natural question that arises is whether the shortest proof of $T$ is a proof by contradiction. That is a much harder question to answer in general, but there are some easy examples, at least for any reasonable natural deduction system.



      For instance, the shortest proof of "$A to A$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely not a proof by contradiction but rather just:




      If $A$:



      $A$.



      Therefore $A to A$, by implication introduction.




      On the other hand, the shortest proof of "$neg ( A land neg A )$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely a proof by contradiction:




      If $A land neg A$:



      $A$, by conjunction elimination.



      $neg A$, by conjunction elimination.



        Thus a contradiction.



      Therefore $neg( A land neg A )$.




      The first part of this post shows that the shortest proof by contradiction is at most a few lines longer than the shortest proof, but nothing much else interesting can be said about the shortest proof unless...





      Well what if we do not allow the use of double negation elimination? If you have only the other usual rules (the first-order logic rules here but excluding ¬¬elim and including ex falso), then the resulting logic is intuitionistic logic, which is strictly weaker than classical logic, and cannot even prove the law of excluded middle, namely "$A lor neg A$" for any statement $A$. So if you instead ask the more interesting question of whether every true theorem can be proven in intuitionistic logic, then the answer is no.



      Note that intuitionistic logic plus the rule "$neg A to bot vdash A$" gives back classical logic, and one could say that this rule embodies the 'true principle' of proof by contradiction, in which case one can say that some true theorems require the use of a proof by contradiction somewhere.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$


















        23












        $begingroup$

        In classical logic, the answer is yes. Take any theorem $T$ and any proof $P$ for $T$. Now write the following proof:




        If $neg T$:



          [Write $P$ here.]



          Thus $T$.



          Thus a contradiction.



        Therefore $neg neg T$, by negation introduction.



        Thus $T$, by double negation elimination.




        One may object that this proof is essentially the same as $P$, and is just wrapped up. That is true, but it is a perfectly legitimate proof of $T$, even if it is longer than $P$, and it is indeed of the form of a proof by contradiction. A natural question that arises is whether the shortest proof of $T$ is a proof by contradiction. That is a much harder question to answer in general, but there are some easy examples, at least for any reasonable natural deduction system.



        For instance, the shortest proof of "$A to A$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely not a proof by contradiction but rather just:




        If $A$:



        $A$.



        Therefore $A to A$, by implication introduction.




        On the other hand, the shortest proof of "$neg ( A land neg A )$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely a proof by contradiction:




        If $A land neg A$:



        $A$, by conjunction elimination.



        $neg A$, by conjunction elimination.



          Thus a contradiction.



        Therefore $neg( A land neg A )$.




        The first part of this post shows that the shortest proof by contradiction is at most a few lines longer than the shortest proof, but nothing much else interesting can be said about the shortest proof unless...





        Well what if we do not allow the use of double negation elimination? If you have only the other usual rules (the first-order logic rules here but excluding ¬¬elim and including ex falso), then the resulting logic is intuitionistic logic, which is strictly weaker than classical logic, and cannot even prove the law of excluded middle, namely "$A lor neg A$" for any statement $A$. So if you instead ask the more interesting question of whether every true theorem can be proven in intuitionistic logic, then the answer is no.



        Note that intuitionistic logic plus the rule "$neg A to bot vdash A$" gives back classical logic, and one could say that this rule embodies the 'true principle' of proof by contradiction, in which case one can say that some true theorems require the use of a proof by contradiction somewhere.






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$
















          23












          23








          23





          $begingroup$

          In classical logic, the answer is yes. Take any theorem $T$ and any proof $P$ for $T$. Now write the following proof:




          If $neg T$:



            [Write $P$ here.]



            Thus $T$.



            Thus a contradiction.



          Therefore $neg neg T$, by negation introduction.



          Thus $T$, by double negation elimination.




          One may object that this proof is essentially the same as $P$, and is just wrapped up. That is true, but it is a perfectly legitimate proof of $T$, even if it is longer than $P$, and it is indeed of the form of a proof by contradiction. A natural question that arises is whether the shortest proof of $T$ is a proof by contradiction. That is a much harder question to answer in general, but there are some easy examples, at least for any reasonable natural deduction system.



          For instance, the shortest proof of "$A to A$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely not a proof by contradiction but rather just:




          If $A$:



          $A$.



          Therefore $A to A$, by implication introduction.




          On the other hand, the shortest proof of "$neg ( A land neg A )$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely a proof by contradiction:




          If $A land neg A$:



          $A$, by conjunction elimination.



          $neg A$, by conjunction elimination.



            Thus a contradiction.



          Therefore $neg( A land neg A )$.




          The first part of this post shows that the shortest proof by contradiction is at most a few lines longer than the shortest proof, but nothing much else interesting can be said about the shortest proof unless...





          Well what if we do not allow the use of double negation elimination? If you have only the other usual rules (the first-order logic rules here but excluding ¬¬elim and including ex falso), then the resulting logic is intuitionistic logic, which is strictly weaker than classical logic, and cannot even prove the law of excluded middle, namely "$A lor neg A$" for any statement $A$. So if you instead ask the more interesting question of whether every true theorem can be proven in intuitionistic logic, then the answer is no.



          Note that intuitionistic logic plus the rule "$neg A to bot vdash A$" gives back classical logic, and one could say that this rule embodies the 'true principle' of proof by contradiction, in which case one can say that some true theorems require the use of a proof by contradiction somewhere.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$



          In classical logic, the answer is yes. Take any theorem $T$ and any proof $P$ for $T$. Now write the following proof:




          If $neg T$:



            [Write $P$ here.]



            Thus $T$.



            Thus a contradiction.



          Therefore $neg neg T$, by negation introduction.



          Thus $T$, by double negation elimination.




          One may object that this proof is essentially the same as $P$, and is just wrapped up. That is true, but it is a perfectly legitimate proof of $T$, even if it is longer than $P$, and it is indeed of the form of a proof by contradiction. A natural question that arises is whether the shortest proof of $T$ is a proof by contradiction. That is a much harder question to answer in general, but there are some easy examples, at least for any reasonable natural deduction system.



          For instance, the shortest proof of "$A to A$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely not a proof by contradiction but rather just:




          If $A$:



          $A$.



          Therefore $A to A$, by implication introduction.




          On the other hand, the shortest proof of "$neg ( A land neg A )$" for any given statement $A$ is definitely a proof by contradiction:




          If $A land neg A$:



          $A$, by conjunction elimination.



          $neg A$, by conjunction elimination.



            Thus a contradiction.



          Therefore $neg( A land neg A )$.




          The first part of this post shows that the shortest proof by contradiction is at most a few lines longer than the shortest proof, but nothing much else interesting can be said about the shortest proof unless...





          Well what if we do not allow the use of double negation elimination? If you have only the other usual rules (the first-order logic rules here but excluding ¬¬elim and including ex falso), then the resulting logic is intuitionistic logic, which is strictly weaker than classical logic, and cannot even prove the law of excluded middle, namely "$A lor neg A$" for any statement $A$. So if you instead ask the more interesting question of whether every true theorem can be proven in intuitionistic logic, then the answer is no.



          Note that intuitionistic logic plus the rule "$neg A to bot vdash A$" gives back classical logic, and one could say that this rule embodies the 'true principle' of proof by contradiction, in which case one can say that some true theorems require the use of a proof by contradiction somewhere.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited Dec 25 '18 at 7:46

























          answered Jan 3 '17 at 6:58









          user21820user21820

          40.4k544163




          40.4k544163























              10












              $begingroup$

              If you can prove a statement $A$ directly, you can prove it by contradiction. Just assume $lnot A$, perform your proof of $A$, note the contradiction, and derive $A$.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                10












                $begingroup$

                If you can prove a statement $A$ directly, you can prove it by contradiction. Just assume $lnot A$, perform your proof of $A$, note the contradiction, and derive $A$.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  10












                  10








                  10





                  $begingroup$

                  If you can prove a statement $A$ directly, you can prove it by contradiction. Just assume $lnot A$, perform your proof of $A$, note the contradiction, and derive $A$.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  If you can prove a statement $A$ directly, you can prove it by contradiction. Just assume $lnot A$, perform your proof of $A$, note the contradiction, and derive $A$.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Jan 3 '17 at 6:10









                  Ross MillikanRoss Millikan

                  302k24201375




                  302k24201375























                      1












                      $begingroup$

                      I find the common thought here unsettling, even if seemingly widely held. Perhaps others share my view, perhaps not (and note, it is just an intuitive view, one which--as explained to me in the comments--isn't in line with the notion of proof!)



                      The proof in these purported proofs by contradiction must necessarily rely on the content of the direct proof. Yes, we have ourselves a contradiction, but in a proof by contradiction what convinces us (i.e., what we count as the proof) is not merely that we have a contradiction, but that we have derived a contradiction in a particular manner--from particular assumption(s)--which leads us to conclude something about these assumptions....that they must not be true.



                      Here, all we do is prove a statement directly from the premises of the argument, and make a note that our conclusion contradicts the conclusion's_negation--leading us to believe that the negation of the conclusion's_negation (i.e., our conclusion) must be true. We then say to ourselves "aha! Indeed this is the case...since we have already (directly) proven our conclusion to be true!"



                      It is not simply that our conclusion need not be derived via contradiction (and that it can be done directly and then "wrapped up" in a so called proof by contradiction), but rather that our conclusion has not been derived in this manner.



                      A contradiction arising in a proof does not necessarily warrant that the method of proof being employed is what we call "proof by contradiction." It is the derivation of this contradiction which warrants the name "proof by contradiction." It is how the contradiction arises. And here, our contradiction doesn't really arise so much as the situation is one in which we are pointing out that a directly derived conclusion is contradictory to its negation.






                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      $endgroup$









                      • 2




                        $begingroup$
                        Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Eric Wofsey
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:10






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:13








                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 4 '17 at 2:28






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:15






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:38


















                      1












                      $begingroup$

                      I find the common thought here unsettling, even if seemingly widely held. Perhaps others share my view, perhaps not (and note, it is just an intuitive view, one which--as explained to me in the comments--isn't in line with the notion of proof!)



                      The proof in these purported proofs by contradiction must necessarily rely on the content of the direct proof. Yes, we have ourselves a contradiction, but in a proof by contradiction what convinces us (i.e., what we count as the proof) is not merely that we have a contradiction, but that we have derived a contradiction in a particular manner--from particular assumption(s)--which leads us to conclude something about these assumptions....that they must not be true.



                      Here, all we do is prove a statement directly from the premises of the argument, and make a note that our conclusion contradicts the conclusion's_negation--leading us to believe that the negation of the conclusion's_negation (i.e., our conclusion) must be true. We then say to ourselves "aha! Indeed this is the case...since we have already (directly) proven our conclusion to be true!"



                      It is not simply that our conclusion need not be derived via contradiction (and that it can be done directly and then "wrapped up" in a so called proof by contradiction), but rather that our conclusion has not been derived in this manner.



                      A contradiction arising in a proof does not necessarily warrant that the method of proof being employed is what we call "proof by contradiction." It is the derivation of this contradiction which warrants the name "proof by contradiction." It is how the contradiction arises. And here, our contradiction doesn't really arise so much as the situation is one in which we are pointing out that a directly derived conclusion is contradictory to its negation.






                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      $endgroup$









                      • 2




                        $begingroup$
                        Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Eric Wofsey
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:10






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:13








                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 4 '17 at 2:28






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:15






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:38
















                      1












                      1








                      1





                      $begingroup$

                      I find the common thought here unsettling, even if seemingly widely held. Perhaps others share my view, perhaps not (and note, it is just an intuitive view, one which--as explained to me in the comments--isn't in line with the notion of proof!)



                      The proof in these purported proofs by contradiction must necessarily rely on the content of the direct proof. Yes, we have ourselves a contradiction, but in a proof by contradiction what convinces us (i.e., what we count as the proof) is not merely that we have a contradiction, but that we have derived a contradiction in a particular manner--from particular assumption(s)--which leads us to conclude something about these assumptions....that they must not be true.



                      Here, all we do is prove a statement directly from the premises of the argument, and make a note that our conclusion contradicts the conclusion's_negation--leading us to believe that the negation of the conclusion's_negation (i.e., our conclusion) must be true. We then say to ourselves "aha! Indeed this is the case...since we have already (directly) proven our conclusion to be true!"



                      It is not simply that our conclusion need not be derived via contradiction (and that it can be done directly and then "wrapped up" in a so called proof by contradiction), but rather that our conclusion has not been derived in this manner.



                      A contradiction arising in a proof does not necessarily warrant that the method of proof being employed is what we call "proof by contradiction." It is the derivation of this contradiction which warrants the name "proof by contradiction." It is how the contradiction arises. And here, our contradiction doesn't really arise so much as the situation is one in which we are pointing out that a directly derived conclusion is contradictory to its negation.






                      share|cite|improve this answer











                      $endgroup$



                      I find the common thought here unsettling, even if seemingly widely held. Perhaps others share my view, perhaps not (and note, it is just an intuitive view, one which--as explained to me in the comments--isn't in line with the notion of proof!)



                      The proof in these purported proofs by contradiction must necessarily rely on the content of the direct proof. Yes, we have ourselves a contradiction, but in a proof by contradiction what convinces us (i.e., what we count as the proof) is not merely that we have a contradiction, but that we have derived a contradiction in a particular manner--from particular assumption(s)--which leads us to conclude something about these assumptions....that they must not be true.



                      Here, all we do is prove a statement directly from the premises of the argument, and make a note that our conclusion contradicts the conclusion's_negation--leading us to believe that the negation of the conclusion's_negation (i.e., our conclusion) must be true. We then say to ourselves "aha! Indeed this is the case...since we have already (directly) proven our conclusion to be true!"



                      It is not simply that our conclusion need not be derived via contradiction (and that it can be done directly and then "wrapped up" in a so called proof by contradiction), but rather that our conclusion has not been derived in this manner.



                      A contradiction arising in a proof does not necessarily warrant that the method of proof being employed is what we call "proof by contradiction." It is the derivation of this contradiction which warrants the name "proof by contradiction." It is how the contradiction arises. And here, our contradiction doesn't really arise so much as the situation is one in which we are pointing out that a directly derived conclusion is contradictory to its negation.







                      share|cite|improve this answer














                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer








                      edited Jan 4 '17 at 6:17

























                      answered Jan 3 '17 at 22:49









                      ParryParry

                      1917




                      1917








                      • 2




                        $begingroup$
                        Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Eric Wofsey
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:10






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:13








                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 4 '17 at 2:28






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:15






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:38
















                      • 2




                        $begingroup$
                        Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Eric Wofsey
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:10






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 3 '17 at 23:13








                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                        $endgroup$
                        – Morgan Rodgers
                        Jan 4 '17 at 2:28






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:15






                      • 1




                        $begingroup$
                        The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                        $endgroup$
                        – user21820
                        Jan 4 '17 at 5:38










                      2




                      2




                      $begingroup$
                      Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Eric Wofsey
                      Jan 3 '17 at 23:10




                      $begingroup$
                      Your intuition makes sense, but raises the challenge of how to precisely define what a "proof by contradiction" actually is then.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Eric Wofsey
                      Jan 3 '17 at 23:10




                      1




                      1




                      $begingroup$
                      The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Morgan Rodgers
                      Jan 3 '17 at 23:13






                      $begingroup$
                      The conclusion that gives you your result in a straightforward proof becomes the conclusion that gives you a contradiction in the new proof. In other words, we can rephrase any proof as a proof by contradiction.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Morgan Rodgers
                      Jan 3 '17 at 23:13






                      1




                      1




                      $begingroup$
                      I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Morgan Rodgers
                      Jan 4 '17 at 2:28




                      $begingroup$
                      I'm not reading the other answers as suggesting to insert a reference to another proof, but rather to repeat the arguments.
                      $endgroup$
                      – Morgan Rodgers
                      Jan 4 '17 at 2:28




                      1




                      1




                      $begingroup$
                      I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                      $endgroup$
                      – user21820
                      Jan 4 '17 at 5:15




                      $begingroup$
                      I meant that it is of a specific syntactic form; it begins with a subproof of a contradiction under an assumption of the form $neg A$, and then deduces $neg neg A$ and then applies DNE to get $A$. So when I said "form" in my answer I do not refer to the notion of "method" that most non-logicians have in mind. Is what I say clearer now?
                      $endgroup$
                      – user21820
                      Jan 4 '17 at 5:15




                      1




                      1




                      $begingroup$
                      The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                      $endgroup$
                      – user21820
                      Jan 4 '17 at 5:38






                      $begingroup$
                      The specific details of the syntactic form will depend on the specific formal system chosen, so you can consider the proof sketch in my answer akin to pseudo-code. If you use the rules in my linked post, then "form of a proof by contradiction" in my answer corresponds to a formal proof whose last 3 lines are of the form: $$¬A→⊥. quad [→intro] \ ¬¬A. quad quad quad [¬intro] \ A. quad quad quad quad [¬¬elim]$$. By the way, your answer is related to mathoverflow.net/questions/3776/….
                      $endgroup$
                      – user21820
                      Jan 4 '17 at 5:38




















                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2081396%2fcan-every-true-theorem-that-has-a-proof-be-proven-by-contradiction%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Plaza Victoria

                      Puebla de Zaragoza

                      Musa