Using relativization to prove relative consistency












1












$begingroup$


Suppose I want to prove that, for some sentence $phi$, $Con(ZFC) to Con(ZFC + phi)$. And to do this, I prove that for some classe $C = { x : psi(x)}$, $C vDash ZFC$ and $C vDash phi$ - using the concept of relativization of formulas. Is this enough to prove the desired result?



I thought it would go along those lines: Supose $(mathbf{M}, E)$ is a model for ZFC and consider the set $mathbf{N} = { a in mathbf{M} : M vDash psi(a) } subseteq mathbf{M} $. Does the relativization argument prove that $(mathbf{N}, E)$ is a model of $ZFC + phi$?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$

















    1












    $begingroup$


    Suppose I want to prove that, for some sentence $phi$, $Con(ZFC) to Con(ZFC + phi)$. And to do this, I prove that for some classe $C = { x : psi(x)}$, $C vDash ZFC$ and $C vDash phi$ - using the concept of relativization of formulas. Is this enough to prove the desired result?



    I thought it would go along those lines: Supose $(mathbf{M}, E)$ is a model for ZFC and consider the set $mathbf{N} = { a in mathbf{M} : M vDash psi(a) } subseteq mathbf{M} $. Does the relativization argument prove that $(mathbf{N}, E)$ is a model of $ZFC + phi$?










    share|cite|improve this question









    $endgroup$















      1












      1








      1





      $begingroup$


      Suppose I want to prove that, for some sentence $phi$, $Con(ZFC) to Con(ZFC + phi)$. And to do this, I prove that for some classe $C = { x : psi(x)}$, $C vDash ZFC$ and $C vDash phi$ - using the concept of relativization of formulas. Is this enough to prove the desired result?



      I thought it would go along those lines: Supose $(mathbf{M}, E)$ is a model for ZFC and consider the set $mathbf{N} = { a in mathbf{M} : M vDash psi(a) } subseteq mathbf{M} $. Does the relativization argument prove that $(mathbf{N}, E)$ is a model of $ZFC + phi$?










      share|cite|improve this question









      $endgroup$




      Suppose I want to prove that, for some sentence $phi$, $Con(ZFC) to Con(ZFC + phi)$. And to do this, I prove that for some classe $C = { x : psi(x)}$, $C vDash ZFC$ and $C vDash phi$ - using the concept of relativization of formulas. Is this enough to prove the desired result?



      I thought it would go along those lines: Supose $(mathbf{M}, E)$ is a model for ZFC and consider the set $mathbf{N} = { a in mathbf{M} : M vDash psi(a) } subseteq mathbf{M} $. Does the relativization argument prove that $(mathbf{N}, E)$ is a model of $ZFC + phi$?







      logic set-theory






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked Dec 24 '18 at 20:16









      Nuntractatuses AmávelNuntractatuses Amável

      635112




      635112






















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          3












          $begingroup$

          Yes, that's correct. Note that strictly speaking, you can't prove (or even state) something like $C vDash ZFC$, since $ZFC$ has infinitely many axioms and you can only relativize one of them at a time. What you can prove is a metatheorem which says that for each individual axiom $psi$ of $ZFC$, $CvDashpsi$ is a theorem of $ZFC$. This is then enough to conclude that $(mathbf{N},E)vDash ZFC$, by interpreting each of these theorems $CvDashpsi$ in the model $(mathbf{M},E)$.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$













          • $begingroup$
            +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 24 '18 at 20:30





















          3












          $begingroup$

          Yup, this is correct - that would do the job. (EDIT: although there is a serious issue here, as pointed out by Eric Wofsey's answer; this is often swept under the rug because its treatment is fairly standard, but it's important to observe at first.)



          It's worth noting however that this isn't the only way to prove consistency, though. In particular, by far the most important technique in set theory for establishing consistency results, forcing, does the opposite: given a countable$^1$ model $M$ of ZFC (which exists if ZFC is consistent, by the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem), forcing gives us a way to try to produce models of ZFC + [desired principle] which are bigger than $M$, rather than looking for a substructure inside $M$.





          $^1$OK, a bit of clarification is necessary since otherwise you might very reasonably be confused if you look at the literature on forcing:




          • In most presentations you'll see the hypothesis that a countable well-founded (or transitive) model of ZFC exists, which is strictly stronger than the mere consistency of ZFC. However, this is unnecessary: forcing can be developed over arbitrary countable models of ZFC without difficulty.


          • A variant of forcing can be developed even over uncountable models of ZFC, where instead of building a literally larger model we produce a more general object - a "Boolean-valued model" - which is still enough for consistency results. This approach actually has a lot of virtues, but it's definitely more technically involved, and one should understand the usual approach to forcing first.


          • Obnoxiously, actual research in set theory tends to be glib about the actual behavior of forcing. Most egregiously, we often talk about the existence of a forcing extension of $V$, the "true universe of all sets," which is clearly nonsense! What's going on here is that we're really using a shorthand for either the Boolean-valued-model or the countable-model approach to forcing, since these are sufficiently well-understood that the translation between them (and the translation of the abuse of language used) is left to the reader. But this is absolutely a huge stumbling block to anyone learning this for the first time. That said, it's also totally addictive: it makes it so much easier to think up forcing arguments, even if the reasoning it produces looks a priori like gibberish!







          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$














            Your Answer








            StackExchange.ready(function() {
            var channelOptions = {
            tags: "".split(" "),
            id: "69"
            };
            initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

            StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
            // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
            if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
            StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
            createEditor();
            });
            }
            else {
            createEditor();
            }
            });

            function createEditor() {
            StackExchange.prepareEditor({
            heartbeatType: 'answer',
            autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
            convertImagesToLinks: true,
            noModals: true,
            showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
            reputationToPostImages: 10,
            bindNavPrevention: true,
            postfix: "",
            imageUploader: {
            brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
            contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
            allowUrls: true
            },
            noCode: true, onDemand: true,
            discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
            ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
            });


            }
            });














            draft saved

            draft discarded


















            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3051595%2fusing-relativization-to-prove-relative-consistency%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown

























            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes








            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes









            3












            $begingroup$

            Yes, that's correct. Note that strictly speaking, you can't prove (or even state) something like $C vDash ZFC$, since $ZFC$ has infinitely many axioms and you can only relativize one of them at a time. What you can prove is a metatheorem which says that for each individual axiom $psi$ of $ZFC$, $CvDashpsi$ is a theorem of $ZFC$. This is then enough to conclude that $(mathbf{N},E)vDash ZFC$, by interpreting each of these theorems $CvDashpsi$ in the model $(mathbf{M},E)$.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













            • $begingroup$
              +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
              $endgroup$
              – Noah Schweber
              Dec 24 '18 at 20:30


















            3












            $begingroup$

            Yes, that's correct. Note that strictly speaking, you can't prove (or even state) something like $C vDash ZFC$, since $ZFC$ has infinitely many axioms and you can only relativize one of them at a time. What you can prove is a metatheorem which says that for each individual axiom $psi$ of $ZFC$, $CvDashpsi$ is a theorem of $ZFC$. This is then enough to conclude that $(mathbf{N},E)vDash ZFC$, by interpreting each of these theorems $CvDashpsi$ in the model $(mathbf{M},E)$.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$













            • $begingroup$
              +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
              $endgroup$
              – Noah Schweber
              Dec 24 '18 at 20:30
















            3












            3








            3





            $begingroup$

            Yes, that's correct. Note that strictly speaking, you can't prove (or even state) something like $C vDash ZFC$, since $ZFC$ has infinitely many axioms and you can only relativize one of them at a time. What you can prove is a metatheorem which says that for each individual axiom $psi$ of $ZFC$, $CvDashpsi$ is a theorem of $ZFC$. This is then enough to conclude that $(mathbf{N},E)vDash ZFC$, by interpreting each of these theorems $CvDashpsi$ in the model $(mathbf{M},E)$.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$



            Yes, that's correct. Note that strictly speaking, you can't prove (or even state) something like $C vDash ZFC$, since $ZFC$ has infinitely many axioms and you can only relativize one of them at a time. What you can prove is a metatheorem which says that for each individual axiom $psi$ of $ZFC$, $CvDashpsi$ is a theorem of $ZFC$. This is then enough to conclude that $(mathbf{N},E)vDash ZFC$, by interpreting each of these theorems $CvDashpsi$ in the model $(mathbf{M},E)$.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered Dec 24 '18 at 20:24









            Eric WofseyEric Wofsey

            194k14222353




            194k14222353












            • $begingroup$
              +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
              $endgroup$
              – Noah Schweber
              Dec 24 '18 at 20:30




















            • $begingroup$
              +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
              $endgroup$
              – Noah Schweber
              Dec 24 '18 at 20:30


















            $begingroup$
            +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 24 '18 at 20:30






            $begingroup$
            +1. To the OP, to get a sense of what the second-to-last sentence here means, look at Montague's reflection principle if you're not familiar with it already; this is an example of a metatheorem which lets us say something about the infinitely-many axioms of ZFC, "from the outside" so to speak.
            $endgroup$
            – Noah Schweber
            Dec 24 '18 at 20:30













            3












            $begingroup$

            Yup, this is correct - that would do the job. (EDIT: although there is a serious issue here, as pointed out by Eric Wofsey's answer; this is often swept under the rug because its treatment is fairly standard, but it's important to observe at first.)



            It's worth noting however that this isn't the only way to prove consistency, though. In particular, by far the most important technique in set theory for establishing consistency results, forcing, does the opposite: given a countable$^1$ model $M$ of ZFC (which exists if ZFC is consistent, by the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem), forcing gives us a way to try to produce models of ZFC + [desired principle] which are bigger than $M$, rather than looking for a substructure inside $M$.





            $^1$OK, a bit of clarification is necessary since otherwise you might very reasonably be confused if you look at the literature on forcing:




            • In most presentations you'll see the hypothesis that a countable well-founded (or transitive) model of ZFC exists, which is strictly stronger than the mere consistency of ZFC. However, this is unnecessary: forcing can be developed over arbitrary countable models of ZFC without difficulty.


            • A variant of forcing can be developed even over uncountable models of ZFC, where instead of building a literally larger model we produce a more general object - a "Boolean-valued model" - which is still enough for consistency results. This approach actually has a lot of virtues, but it's definitely more technically involved, and one should understand the usual approach to forcing first.


            • Obnoxiously, actual research in set theory tends to be glib about the actual behavior of forcing. Most egregiously, we often talk about the existence of a forcing extension of $V$, the "true universe of all sets," which is clearly nonsense! What's going on here is that we're really using a shorthand for either the Boolean-valued-model or the countable-model approach to forcing, since these are sufficiently well-understood that the translation between them (and the translation of the abuse of language used) is left to the reader. But this is absolutely a huge stumbling block to anyone learning this for the first time. That said, it's also totally addictive: it makes it so much easier to think up forcing arguments, even if the reasoning it produces looks a priori like gibberish!







            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$


















              3












              $begingroup$

              Yup, this is correct - that would do the job. (EDIT: although there is a serious issue here, as pointed out by Eric Wofsey's answer; this is often swept under the rug because its treatment is fairly standard, but it's important to observe at first.)



              It's worth noting however that this isn't the only way to prove consistency, though. In particular, by far the most important technique in set theory for establishing consistency results, forcing, does the opposite: given a countable$^1$ model $M$ of ZFC (which exists if ZFC is consistent, by the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem), forcing gives us a way to try to produce models of ZFC + [desired principle] which are bigger than $M$, rather than looking for a substructure inside $M$.





              $^1$OK, a bit of clarification is necessary since otherwise you might very reasonably be confused if you look at the literature on forcing:




              • In most presentations you'll see the hypothesis that a countable well-founded (or transitive) model of ZFC exists, which is strictly stronger than the mere consistency of ZFC. However, this is unnecessary: forcing can be developed over arbitrary countable models of ZFC without difficulty.


              • A variant of forcing can be developed even over uncountable models of ZFC, where instead of building a literally larger model we produce a more general object - a "Boolean-valued model" - which is still enough for consistency results. This approach actually has a lot of virtues, but it's definitely more technically involved, and one should understand the usual approach to forcing first.


              • Obnoxiously, actual research in set theory tends to be glib about the actual behavior of forcing. Most egregiously, we often talk about the existence of a forcing extension of $V$, the "true universe of all sets," which is clearly nonsense! What's going on here is that we're really using a shorthand for either the Boolean-valued-model or the countable-model approach to forcing, since these are sufficiently well-understood that the translation between them (and the translation of the abuse of language used) is left to the reader. But this is absolutely a huge stumbling block to anyone learning this for the first time. That said, it's also totally addictive: it makes it so much easier to think up forcing arguments, even if the reasoning it produces looks a priori like gibberish!







              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$
















                3












                3








                3





                $begingroup$

                Yup, this is correct - that would do the job. (EDIT: although there is a serious issue here, as pointed out by Eric Wofsey's answer; this is often swept under the rug because its treatment is fairly standard, but it's important to observe at first.)



                It's worth noting however that this isn't the only way to prove consistency, though. In particular, by far the most important technique in set theory for establishing consistency results, forcing, does the opposite: given a countable$^1$ model $M$ of ZFC (which exists if ZFC is consistent, by the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem), forcing gives us a way to try to produce models of ZFC + [desired principle] which are bigger than $M$, rather than looking for a substructure inside $M$.





                $^1$OK, a bit of clarification is necessary since otherwise you might very reasonably be confused if you look at the literature on forcing:




                • In most presentations you'll see the hypothesis that a countable well-founded (or transitive) model of ZFC exists, which is strictly stronger than the mere consistency of ZFC. However, this is unnecessary: forcing can be developed over arbitrary countable models of ZFC without difficulty.


                • A variant of forcing can be developed even over uncountable models of ZFC, where instead of building a literally larger model we produce a more general object - a "Boolean-valued model" - which is still enough for consistency results. This approach actually has a lot of virtues, but it's definitely more technically involved, and one should understand the usual approach to forcing first.


                • Obnoxiously, actual research in set theory tends to be glib about the actual behavior of forcing. Most egregiously, we often talk about the existence of a forcing extension of $V$, the "true universe of all sets," which is clearly nonsense! What's going on here is that we're really using a shorthand for either the Boolean-valued-model or the countable-model approach to forcing, since these are sufficiently well-understood that the translation between them (and the translation of the abuse of language used) is left to the reader. But this is absolutely a huge stumbling block to anyone learning this for the first time. That said, it's also totally addictive: it makes it so much easier to think up forcing arguments, even if the reasoning it produces looks a priori like gibberish!







                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$



                Yup, this is correct - that would do the job. (EDIT: although there is a serious issue here, as pointed out by Eric Wofsey's answer; this is often swept under the rug because its treatment is fairly standard, but it's important to observe at first.)



                It's worth noting however that this isn't the only way to prove consistency, though. In particular, by far the most important technique in set theory for establishing consistency results, forcing, does the opposite: given a countable$^1$ model $M$ of ZFC (which exists if ZFC is consistent, by the downward Lowenheim-Skolem theorem), forcing gives us a way to try to produce models of ZFC + [desired principle] which are bigger than $M$, rather than looking for a substructure inside $M$.





                $^1$OK, a bit of clarification is necessary since otherwise you might very reasonably be confused if you look at the literature on forcing:




                • In most presentations you'll see the hypothesis that a countable well-founded (or transitive) model of ZFC exists, which is strictly stronger than the mere consistency of ZFC. However, this is unnecessary: forcing can be developed over arbitrary countable models of ZFC without difficulty.


                • A variant of forcing can be developed even over uncountable models of ZFC, where instead of building a literally larger model we produce a more general object - a "Boolean-valued model" - which is still enough for consistency results. This approach actually has a lot of virtues, but it's definitely more technically involved, and one should understand the usual approach to forcing first.


                • Obnoxiously, actual research in set theory tends to be glib about the actual behavior of forcing. Most egregiously, we often talk about the existence of a forcing extension of $V$, the "true universe of all sets," which is clearly nonsense! What's going on here is that we're really using a shorthand for either the Boolean-valued-model or the countable-model approach to forcing, since these are sufficiently well-understood that the translation between them (and the translation of the abuse of language used) is left to the reader. But this is absolutely a huge stumbling block to anyone learning this for the first time. That said, it's also totally addictive: it makes it so much easier to think up forcing arguments, even if the reasoning it produces looks a priori like gibberish!








                share|cite|improve this answer














                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer








                edited Dec 24 '18 at 20:34

























                answered Dec 24 '18 at 20:22









                Noah SchweberNoah Schweber

                129k10155296




                129k10155296






























                    draft saved

                    draft discarded




















































                    Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                    • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                    But avoid



                    • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                    • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                    Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                    To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                    draft saved


                    draft discarded














                    StackExchange.ready(
                    function () {
                    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3051595%2fusing-relativization-to-prove-relative-consistency%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                    }
                    );

                    Post as a guest















                    Required, but never shown





















































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown

































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown







                    Popular posts from this blog

                    Plaza Victoria

                    Puebla de Zaragoza

                    Musa